Marx and socialist anti-politics

“A bird’s eye view of a community, as proposed by Robert Owen”. Engraving by F. Bate, published by The Association of all Classes of all Nations, London: 1838. Wikimedia Commons.

Essay

Marx and socialist anti-politics

By Bruno Leipold

Scroll to Article Content

Socialists believe in economic emancipation from the domination and unfreedom of capitalism. But realising that monumental economic goal invariably and inescapably requires socialists to think about what political means, if any, might bring it about. In the long history of anti-capitalist struggle, socialists have given very different answers to that question.

In March 1835, amid growing working-class struggle for reform of Britain’s oligarchic constitution that excluded them from political participation, the Welsh socialist Robert Owen intervened to give one answer to the question. He counselled workers that “It is not Universal Suffrage, Vote by [secret] Ballot, and Annual Parliaments that can effect that which is now required for the people of all countries.” Instead, they “could insure their emancipation from their present sufferings by a much shorter and surer course than through political agitation.” 

The alternative course was one that Owen had been preaching for close to twenty years. In place of political agitation, he advocated the creation of small intentional communities where some 500-2000 people would live and work cooperatively together in a large square set of buildings—or “parallelogram” as he referred to it. Owen had himself tried to set up several such communities in England and the United States. He was entirely convinced that they would attract support from all classes, spread across the world and peacefully bring about a new socialist society.

Owen’s intervention drew an immediate sharp rebuke from Bronterre O’Brien, a social republican and leading Chartist (the working-class movement campaigning for democratic reform).  â€śThe idea of cajoling a rich man out of his present enjoyments by telling him he will be more happy in a parallelogram”, O’Brien retorted, ”appears to us the most complete hallucination that can enter the mind of man.” Sceptical of some of Owen’s more far-reaching socialist ideas on abolishing private property, O’Brien nonetheless held that emancipation from capitalism’s “bastard despotism” could not bypass the battle for political reform. For O’Brien, there could be no expectation of social emancipation under “the present aristocratic Government”, for “under no Government but an extreme democracy is there slightest chance of its success.”

Karl Marx was a 16-year-old schoolboy in the Prussian Rhineland when these debates between republicans and socialists were taking place in Britain. When he entered the public sphere seven years later as a journalist in 1842, he did so as a republican who shared the kind of criticisms O’Brien had made of existing socialists. Marx similarly objected to socialism’s obsession with abolishing private property and especially attacked their neglect of political matters. “The critic,” Marx insisted, “not only can but must engage in these political questions (which according to the views of the crass socialists are beneath their dignity).”

When Marx transitioned to communism a few months after writing these words he carried with him his prior republican political commitments. He set out to fashion a new republican socialism, that married the belief in abolishing capitalist private property to a commitment to the centrality of democratic politics in bringing it about. That involved, on the one hand, a critique of republicans who thought capitalism could be resisted by universalising private property through the small-scale independent production of artisans and peasants (which Marx thought entirely failed to recognise the productive efficiency and dynamism of large-scale industrial capitalism). 

But it also involved a critique of the deeply anti-political tendencies of early socialism. In The Communist Manifesto, Marx (and Engels), attacked Owen for believing that class antagonisms could be overcome by “the force of example” of his parallelogram communities. This naïve belief led Owen and other socialists to engage in “bitter opposition to the political action of the working class” including the Chartist struggle for democracy. Instead, Marx and Engels argued that “the first step” in the working class’s struggle for socialism had to be “win[ing] the battle for democracy.”

This deep commitment to politics and democracy contrasts with how Marx is usually presented to us. Public commentators repeat endless incantations of “…as the Soviet Union proved…” to exorcise any discussion of Marx, socialism and democracy. While a favoured framing device amongst academic critics of Marx is to depict him as the anti-political thinker par excellence, who subordinated everything to the economy. Understanding Marx in his nineteenth-century context and his attempt to displace the anti-political and anti-democratic tendencies in early socialism, shows how baseless these interpretations are. Democracy and politics were, for Marx, essential elements in the struggle for socialism.

What kind of democratic political structures did Marx think were required for socialism? It certainly included familiar institutions like universal suffrage and equal civic rights. But in response to the 1871 Paris Commune—when the city’s working class briefly took power and led a radical democratic experiment—Marx sketched a much more far-reaching account of popular democracy. Representatives should be paid the same wages as workers and elected much more frequently (an echo of the Chartist demand for annual parliaments) and constituents should in turn be able to give representatives binding instructions and have the power to recall them. This would mean that “Instead of deciding once in three or six years which member of the ruling class was to misrepresent the people in Parliament, universal suffrage was to serve the people.” State bureaucrats were to be similarly elected and recallable, turning “the haughteous masters of the people into its always removable servants, a mock responsibility by a real responsibility, as they act continuously under public supervision.” 

It was these radical democratic institutions that Marx thought would provide the appropriate political terrain for ending the economic unfreedom and domination of capitalism.  In a moment when “democracy” is under siege on all sides and seemingly unable to deal with capitalism’s despotic and destructive rule over people, politics and the planet, Marx’s thought might be one unlikely resource for re-thinking democracy’s defining institutions. 

Illustration of Marx amid crowd holding "Capital" and pointing towards an island across the ocean. A sun over the island reads "Liberté, égalité, fraternité". Along the shoreline are ships with sails which include statements such as "suffrage universel et référendum".
Marx depicted guiding the way to the socialist-republican future of liberty, equality and fraternity via the means of universal suffrage. “La Terre promise (The Promised Land)”, Le Figaro-Graphic (1 May 1892). Courtesy of Bibliothèque Nationale de France.


Bruno Leipold is a fellow in political theory at the London School of Economics and Political Science. He is the coeditor of Radical Republicanism: Recovering the Tradition’s Popular Heritage.